Preview Extract
INSTRUCTORโS
SOLUTIONS MANUAL
F OUNDATIONS OF G EOMETRY
SECOND EDITION
Gerard A. Venema
Calvin College
Boston Columbus Indianapolis New York San Francisco Upper Saddle River
Amsterdam Cape Town Dubai London Madrid Milan Munich Paris Montreal Toronto
Delhi Mexico City Sao Paulo Sydney Hong Kong Seoul Singapore Taipei Tokyo
The author and publisher of this book have used their best efforts in preparing this book. These efforts include the
development, research, and testing of the theories and programs to determine their effectiveness. The author and
publisher make no warranty of any kind, expressed or implied, with regard to these programs or the documentation
contained in this book. The author and publisher shall not be liable in any event for incidental or consequential
damages in connection with, or arising out of, the furnishing, performance, or use of these programs.
Reproduced by Pearson from electronic files supplied by the author.
Copyright ยฉ 2012 Pearson Education, Inc.
Publishing as Pearson, 75 Arlington Street, Boston, MA 02116.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any
form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior written
permission of the publisher. Printed in the United States of America.
ISBN 0136020593
1 2 3 4 5 6 XX 15 14 13 12 11
www.pearsonhighered.com
i
i
Contents
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 1
1
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 2
6
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 3
14
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 4
27
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 5
50
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 6
72
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 7
86
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 8
96
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 10
106
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 11
127
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 12
137
Bibliography
143
ii
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
i
i
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 1
1.6.1 Check that the formula A D 1 .a C c/.b C d/ works for rectangles but not for
4
parallelograms.
b
b
a
c
a
c
d
d
FIGURE S1.1: Exercise 1.6.1. A rectangle and a parallelogram
For rectangles and parallelograms, a D c and b D d and Area = baseโheight.
For a rectangle, the base and the height will be equal to the lengths of two adjacent
sides. Therefore A D a โ d D 1 .a C a/ โ 1 .b C b/ D 1 .a C c/.b C d/
2
2
4
In the case of a parallelogram, the height is smaller than the length of the side so
the formula does not give the correct answer.
1.6.2 The area of a circle is given by the formula A D ฯ. d /2 . According the Egyptians,
2
A is also equal to the area of a square with sides equal to 8 d; thus A D . 8 /2 d 2 .
9
9
Equating and solving for ฯ gives
ฯD
. 8 /2 d 2
9
1 2
d
4
64
256
D 81
D
1
81
4
L 3.160494.
1.6.3 The sum of the measures of the two acute angles in ^ABC is 90โฆ , so the first shaded
region is a square. We must show that the area of the shaded region in the first
square .c2 / is equal to the area of the shaded region in the second square .a2 C b2 /.
The two large squares have the same area because they both have side length
a C b. Also each of these squares contains four copies of triangle ^ABC (in
white). Therefore, by subtraction, the shadesd regions must have equal area and so
a2 C b 2 D c 2 .
1.6.4
(a) Suppose a D u2 โ v2 , b D 2uv and c D u2 C v2 . We must show that
a2 C b2 D c2 . First, a2 C b2 D .u2 โ v2 /2 C .2uv/2 D u4 โ 2u2 v2 C v4 C
4u2 v2 D u4 C 2u2 v2 C v4 and, second, c2 D .u2 C v2 /2 D u4 C 2u2 v2 C v4 D
u4 C 2u2 v2 C v4 . So a2 C b2 D c2 .
(b) Let u and v be odd. We will show that a, b and c are all even. Since u and v are
both odd, we know that u2 and v2 are also odd. Therefore a D u2 โ v2 is even
(the difference between two odd numbers is even). It is obvious that b D 2uv
is even, and c D u2 C v2 is also even since it is the sum of two odd numbers.
(c) Suppose one of u and v is even and the other is odd. We will show that a, b,
and c do not have any common prime factors. Now a and c are both odd, so 2
is not a factor of a or c. Suppose x Z 2 is a prime factor of b. Then either x
divides u or x divides v, but not both because u and v are relatively prime. If
x divides u, then it also divides u2 but not v2 . Thus x is not a factor of a or c.
1
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
i
i
2
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 1
If x divides v, then it divides v2 but not u2 . Again x is not a factor of a or c.
Therefore .a, b, c/ is a primitive Pythagorean triple.
1.6.5 Let h C x be the height of the entire (untruncated) pyramid. We know that
h C x
a
D
x
b
b
(algebra). The volume of the
a โ b
truncated pyramid is the volume of the whole pyramid minus the volume of the top
pyramid. Therefore
(by the Similar Triangles Theorem), so x D h
1
1
.h C x/a2 โ xb2
3
3
1
b
1
b3
D .h C h
/a2 โ h.
/
3
a โ b
3 a โ b
h
a2 b
h
b3
D .a2 C
/ โ .
/
3
a โ b
3 a โ b
h
a2 b โ b3
D .a2 C
/
3
a โ b
.a โ b/.ab C b2 /
h
D .a2 C
/
3
.a โ b/
h
D .a2 C ab C b2 /.
3
V D
x
b
b
h
a
a
FIGURE S1.2: Exercise 1.6.5. A truncated pyramid.
1.6.6 Constructions using a compass and a straightedge. There are numerous ways in
which to accomplish each of these constructions; just one is indicated in each case.
(a) The perpendicular bisector of a line segment AB.
Using the compass, construct two circles, the first about A through B, the
second about B through A. Then use the straightedge to construct a line
through the two points created by the intersection of the two circles.
(b) A line through a point P perpendicular to a line `.
Use the compass to construct a circle about P, making sure the circle is big
enough so that it intersects ` at two points, A and B. Then construct the
perpendicular bisector of segment AB as in part (a).
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
i
i
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 1
3
B
A
FIGURE S1.3: Exercise 1.6(a) Construction of a perpendicular bisector
P
โ
A
B
FIGURE S1.4: Exercise 1.6.6(b) Construction of a line through P, perpendicular to `
(c) The angle bisector of jBAC.
Using the compass, construct a circle about A that intersects AB and AC.
Call those points of intersection D and E respectively. Then construct the
perpendicular bisector of DE. This line is the angle bisector.
1.6.7
(a) No. Euclidโs postulates say nothing about the number of points on a line.
(b) No.
(c) No. The postulates only assert that there is a line; they do not say there is only
one.
1.6.8 The proof of Proposition 29.
1.6.9 Let nABCD be a rhombus (all four sides are equal), and let E be the point of
intersection between AC and DB.1 We must show that ^AEB > ^CEB > ^CED >
^AED. Now jBAC > jACB and jCAD > jACD by Proposition 5. By addition
we can see that jBAD > jBCD and similarly, jADC > jABC. Now we know that
^ABC > ^ADC by Proposition 4. Similarly, ^DBA > ^DBC. This implies that
jBAC > jDAC > jBCA > jDCA and jBDA > jDBA > jBDC > jDBC.
1 In this solution and the next, the existence of the point E is taken for granted. Its existence
is obvious from the diagram. Proving that E exists is one of the gaps that must be filled in these
proofs. This point will be addressed in Chapter 6.
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
i
i
4
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 1
D
B
A
E
C
FIGURE S1.5: Exercise 1.6.6(c) Construction of an angle bisector
Thus ^AEB > ^AED > ^CEB > ^CED, again by Proposition 4.2
D
C
E
A
B
FIGURE S1.6: Exercise 1.6.9 Rhombus nABCD
1.6.10 Let nABCD be a rectangle, and let E be the point of intersection of AC and BD. We
must prove that AC > BD and that AC and BD bisect each other (i.e., AE > EC
(‘ (‘
(‘ (‘
and BE > ED). By Proposition 28, DA k CB and DC k AB . Therefore, by
Proposition 29, jCAB > jACD and jDAC > jACB. Hence ^ABC > ^CDA
and ^ADB > ^CBD by Proposition 26 (ASA). Since those triangles are congruent
we know that opposite sides of the rectangle are congruent and ^ABD > ^BAC
(by Proposition 4), and therefore BD > AC.
Now we must prove that the segments bisect each other. By Proposition 29,
jCAB > jACD and jDBA > jBDC. Hence ^ABE > ^CDE (by Proposition 26)
which implies that AE > CE and DE > BE. Therefore the diagonals are equal and
bisect each other.
1.6.11 The argument works for the first case. This is the case in which the triangle actually
is isosceles. The second case never occurs (D is never inside the triangle). The flaw
lies in the third case (D is outside the triangle). If the triangle is not isosceles then
either E will be outside the triangle and F will be on the edge AC, or E will be on
the edge AB and F will be outside. They cannot both be outside as shown in the
diagram. This can be checked by drawing a careful diagram by hand or by drawing
the diagram using GeoGebra (or similar software).
2 It should be noted that the fact about rhombi can be proved using just propositions that come
early in Book I and do not depend on the Fifth Postulate, whereas the proof in the next exercise
requires propositions about parallelism that Euclid proves much later in Book I using his Fifth
Postulate.
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
i
i
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 1
D
C
E
A
B
FIGURE S1.7: Exercise 1.6.10 Rectangle nABCD
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
5
i
i
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 2
2.4.1 This is not a model for Incidence Geometry since it does not satisfy Incidence
Axiom 3. This example is isomorphic to the 3-point line.
2.4.2 One-point Geometry satisfies Axioms 1 and 2 but not Axiom 3. Every pair of
distinct points defines a unique line (vacuouslyโthere is no pair of distinct points).
There do not exist three distinct points, so there cannot be three noncollinear points.
One-point Geometry satisfies all three parallel postulates (vacuouslyโthere is no
line).
2.4.3 It helps to draw a schematic diagram of the relationships.
(a)
(c)
(b)
A
A
A
B
B
B
C
C
D
D
D
C
FIGURE S2.1: A schematic representation of the committee structures
(a) Not a model. There is no line containing B and D. There are two lines
containing B and C.
(b) Not a model. There is no line containing C and D.
(c) Not a model. There is no line containing A and D.
(a) The Three-point plane is a model for Three-point geometry.
(b) Every model for Three-point geometry has 3 lines. If there are 3 points, then
there are also 3 pairs of points
(c) Suppose there are two models for Three-point geometry, model A and
model B. Choose any 1-1 correspondence of the points in model A to the
points in model B. Any line in A is determined by two points. These two
points correspond to two points in B. Those two points determine a line in B.
The isomorphism should map the given line in A to this line in B. Then the
function will preserve betweennes. Therefore models A and B are isomorphic
to one another.
2.4.5 Axiom 1 does not hold, but Axioms 2 and 3 do. The Euclidean Parallel Postulate
holds. The other parallel postulates are false in this interpretation.
2.4.6 See Figure S2.2.
2.4.7 Fanoโs Geometry satisfies the Elliptic Parallel Postulate because every line shares
at least one point with every other line; there are no parallel lines. It does not satisfy
either of the other parallel postulates.
2.4.8 The three-point line satisfies all three parallel postulates (vacuously).
2.4.9 If there are so few points and lines that there is no line with an external point,
then all three parallel postulates are satisfied (vacuously). If there is a line with an
external point, then there will either be a parallel line through the external point or
there will not be. Hence at most one of the parallel postulates can be satisfied in
2.4.4
6
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
i
i
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 2
7
FIGURE S2.2: Five-point Geometry
that case. Since every incidence geometry contains three noncollinear points, there
must be a line with an external point. Hence an incidence geometry can satisfy at
most one of the parallel postulates.
2.10 Start with a line with three points on it. There must exist another point not on that
line (Incidence Axiom 3). That point, together with the points on the original line,
determines three more lines (Incidence Axiom 1). But each of those lines must
have a third point on it. So there must be at least three more points, for a total of
at least seven points. Since Fanoโs Geometry has exactly seven points, seven is the
minimum.
2.4.11 See Figures S2.3 and S2.4.
FIGURE S2.3: An unbalanced geometry
FIGURE S2.4: A simpler example
2.4.12
(a) The three-point line (Example 2.2.3).
(b) The square (Exercise 2.4.5) or the sphere (Example 2.2.9).
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
i
i
8
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 2
2.4.13
(c) One-point geometry (Exercise 2.4.2).
(a) The dual of the Three-point plane is another Three-point plane. It is a model
for incidence geometry.
(b) The dual of the Three-point line is a point which is incident with 3 lines. This
is not a model for incidence geometry.
(c) The dual of Four-point Geometry has 6 points and 4 lines. Each point is
incident with exactly 2 lines, and each line is incident with 3 points. It is not a
model for incidence geometry because it does not satisfy Incidence Axiom 1.
(d) The dual of Fanoโs Geometry is isomorphic to Fanoโs Geometry, so it is a
model for incidence geometry.
2.5.1
(a) H : it rains
C : I get wet
(b) H : the sun shines
C : we go hiking and biking
(c) H : x > 0
C : E a y such that y2 D 0
(d) H : 2x C 1 D 5
C : x D 2 or x D 3
2.5.2
(a) Converse : If I get wet, then it rained.
Contrapositive : If I do not get wet, then it did not rain.
(b) Converse : If we go hiking and biking, then the sun shines.
Contrapositive : If we do not go hiking and biking, then the sun does not shine.
(c) Converse : If E a y such that y2 D 0, then x > 0.
Contrapositive : If 5 y, y2 Z 0, then x โค 0.
(d) Converse : If x D 2 or x D 3, then 2x C 1 D 5.
Contrapositive : If x Z 2 and x Z 3, then 2x C 1 Z 5
2.5.3
(a) It rains and I do not get wet.
(b) The sun shines but we do not go hiking or biking.
(c) x > 0 and 5y, y2 Z 0.
(d) 2x C 1 D 5 but x is not equal to 2 or 3.
2.5.4
(a) If the grade is an A, then the score is at least 90%.
(b) If the score is at least 50%, then the grade is a passing grade.
(c) If you fail, then you scored less than 50%.
(d) If you try hard, then you succeed.
2.5.5
(a) Converse: If the score is at least 90%, then the grade is an A.
Contrapositive: If the score is less than 90%, then the grade is not an A.
(b) Converse: If the grade is a passing grade, then the score is at least 50%.
Contrapositive: If the grades is not a passing grade, then the score is less than
50%.
(c) Converse: If you score less than 50%, then you fail.
Contrapositive: If you score at least 50%, then you pass.
(d) Converse: If you succeed, then you tried hard.
Contrapositive: If you do not succeed, then you did not try hard.
2.5.6
(a) The grade is an A but the score is less than 90%.
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
i
i
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 2
9
(b) The grade is at least 50% but the grade is not a passing grade.
(c) You fail and your score is at least 50%.
(d) You try hard but do not succeed.
2.5.8
(a) H : I pass geometry
C : I can take topology
(b) H : it rains
C : I get wet
(c) H : the number x is divisible by 4
C : x is even
2.5.9
(a) 5 triangles T , the angle sum of T is 180โฆ .
(b) E triangle T such that the angle sum of T is less than 180โฆ .
(c) E triangle T such that the angle sum of T is not equal to 180โฆ .
(d) 5 great circles ฮฑ and ฮฒ, ฮฑ โฉ ฮฒ Z โ
.
(e) 5 point P and 5 line ` E line m such that P lies on ` and m ‘ `.
2.5.10
(a) 5 model for incidence geometry, the Euclidean Parallel Postulate does not
hold in that model.
(b) E a model for incidence geometry in which there are not exactly 7 points (the
number of points is either โค 6 or โฅ 8).
(c) E a triangle whose angle sum is not 180โฆ .
(d) E a triangle whose angle sum is at least 180โฆ .
(e) It is not hot or it is not humid outside.
(f) My favorite color is not red and it is not green.
(g) The sun shines and (but?) we do not go hiking. (See explanation in last full
paragraph on page 36.)
(h) E a geometry student who does not know how to write proofs.
2.5.11
(a) Negation of Euclidean Parallel Postulate. There exist a line ` and a point P not
on ` such that either there is no line m such that P lies on m and m is parallel
to ` or there are (at least) two lines m and n such that P lies on both m and n,
m k `, and n k `.
(b) Negation of Elliptic Parallel Postulate. There exist a line ` and a point P that
does not lie on ` such that there is at least one line m such that P lies on m and
m k `.
(c) Negation of Hyperbolic Parallel Postulate. There exist a line ` and a point P
that does not lie on ` such that either there is no line m such that P lies on m
and m k ` or there is exactly one line m with these properties.
Note. You could emphasize the separate existence of ` and P by starting each of the
statements above with, โโThere exist a line ` and there exists a point P not on ` such
that ….โโ
2.5.12 not (S and T ) K (not S) or (not T ).
S
T
S and T not (S and T )
True True
True
False
True False
False
True
False True
False
True
False False
False
True
not S
False
False
True
True
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
not T
False
True
False
True
(not C) or (not H)
False
True
True
True
i
i
10
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 2
not (S or T ) K (not S) and (not T ).
S
T
S or T not (S or T )
True True
True
False
True
False
True False
False True
True
False
True
False False False
not S
False
False
True
True
not T
False
True
False
True
(not C) and (not H)
False
False
False
True
2.5.13 H * C K (not H) or C.
H
C
H * C not H (not H) or C
True True
True
False
True
True False
False
False
False
True
True
True
False True
False False
True
True
True
By De Morgan, not (H and (not C)) is logically equivalent to (not H) or C.
2.5.14 not (H * C) K (H and (not C)).
H
C
H * C not(H * C)
True True
True
False
True False
False
True
False True
True
False
False False
True
False
not C
False
True
False
True
H and (not C)
False
True
False
False
2.5.15 If ^ABC is right triangle with right angle at vertex C, and a, b, and c are the lengths
of the sides opposite vertices A, B, and C respectively, then a2 C b2 D c2 .
2.5.16
(a) Euclidean. If ` is a line and P is a point that does not lie on `, then there exists
exactly one line m such that P lies on m and m k `.
(b) Elliptic. If ` is a line and P is a point that does not lie on `, then there does not
exist a line m such that P lies on m and m k `.
(c) Hyperbolic. If ` is a line and P is a point that does not lie on `, then there exist
at least two distinct lines m and n such that P lies on both m and n and ` is
parallel to both m and n.
2.6.1 Converse to Theorem 2.6.2.
Proof. Let ` and m be two lines (notation). Assume there exists exactly one point
that lies on both ` and m (hypothesis). We must show that ` Z m and ` โฆ m.
Suppose ` D m (RAA hypothesis). There exists two distinct points Q and R that
lie on ` (Incidence Axiom 2). Since m D `, Q and R lie on both ` and m. This
contradicts the hypothesis that ` and m intersect in exactly one point, so we can
reject the RAA hypothesis and conclude that ` Z m.
Since ` and m have a point in common, ` โฆ m (definition of parallel).
(‘
Note. In the next few proofs it is convenient to introduce the notation AB for the
line determined by A and B (Incidence Axiom 1). This notation is not defined in the
textbook until Chapter 3, but it fits with Incidence Axiom 1 and allows the proofs
below to be written more succinctly.
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
i
i
Solutions to Exercises in Chapter 2
11
2.6.2 Theorem 2.6.3.
Proof. Let ` be a line (hypothesis). We must prove that there exists a point P such
that P does not lie on `. There exist three noncollinear points A, B, and C (Axiom 3).
The three points A, B and C cannot all lie on ` because if they did then they would
be collinear (definition of collinear). Hence at least one of them does not lie on `
and the proof is complete.
Note. Many (or most) students will get the last proof wrong. The reason is that
they want to assume some relationship between the line given in the hypothesis of
the theorem and the points given by Axiom 3. In particular, many students will
start with the first three sentences of the proof above, but will then either assert or
(‘
assume that ` D AB .
This is an important opportunity to point out that the axioms mean exactly what they
say and we must be careful not to impose our own assumptions on them. The fact
that we are imposing an unstated assumption on the axioms is often covered up by
the fact that the same letters are used for the three points given by Axiom 3 and the
two points given by Axiom 2. So this exercise is also an opportunity to discuss notation and how we assign names to mathematical objects. (The fact that we happen to
use the same letter to name two different points does not make them the same point.)
Similar comments apply to the next three proofs.
2.6.3 Theorem 2.6.4.
Proof. Let P be a point (hypothesis). We must show that there are two distinct
lines ` and m such that P lies on both ` and m. There exist three noncollinear points
A, B, and C (Axiom 3). There are two cases to consider: either P is equal to one of
the three points A, B, and C or it is not.
(‘
(‘
Suppose, first, that P D A. Define ` D AB and m D AC (Axiom 1). Obviously
P D A lies on both these lines. It cannot be that ` D m because in that case A, B,
and C would be collinear. So the proof of this case is complete. The proofs of the
cases in which P D B and P D C are similar.
Now suppose that P is distinct from all three of the points A, B, and C. In that
(‘
(‘
(‘
case we can define three lines ` D PA , m D PB , and n D PC (Axiom 1). These
three lines cannot all be the same because if they were then A, B, and C would be
collinear. Therefore at least two of them are distinct and the proof is complete.
Note. Many students will assert that the three lines in the last paragraph are distinct.
But that is not necessarily the case, as Fig. S2.5 shows.
Outline of an alternative proof: Find one line ` such that P lies on `. Then use the
previous theorem to find a point R that does not lie on `. The line through P and
R is the second line. This proof is simpler and better than the one given above, but
most students do not think of it. You might want to lead them in that direction
by suggesting that they prove the existence of one line first rather than proving the
existence of both at the same time.
Copyright ยฉ 2013 Pearson Education, Inc.
Document Preview (14 of 146 Pages)
User generated content is uploaded by users for the purposes of learning and should be used following SchloarOn's honor code & terms of service.
You are viewing preview pages of the document. Purchase to get full access instantly.
-37%
Solution Manual for Foundations of Geometry, 2nd Edition
$18.99 $29.99Save:$11.00(37%)
24/7 Live Chat
Instant Download
100% Confidential
Store
Lucas Clark
0 (0 Reviews)
Best Selling
Test Bank for Strategies For Reading Assessment And Instruction: Helping Every Child Succeed, 6th Edition
$18.99 $29.99Save:$11.00(37%)
Chemistry: Principles And Reactions, 7th Edition Test Bank
$18.99 $29.99Save:$11.00(37%)
The World Of Customer Service, 3rd Edition Test Bank
$18.99 $29.99Save:$11.00(37%)
Solution Manual for Designing the User Interface: Strategies for Effective Human-Computer Interaction, 6th Edition
$18.99 $29.99Save:$11.00(37%)
Data Structures and Other Objects Using C++ 4th Edition Solution Manual
$18.99 $29.99Save:$11.00(37%)
2023-2024 ATI Pediatrics Proctored Exam with Answers (139 Solved Questions)
$18.99 $29.99Save:$11.00(37%)